derived.tex 18.1 KB
Newer Older
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
1
\section{Derived proof rules and other constructions}
2
3
4

\subsection{Base logic}

Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
5
6
7
8
9
10
We collect here some important and frequently used derived proof rules.
\begin{mathparpagebreakable}
  \infer{}
  {\prop \Ra \propB \proves \prop \wand \propB}

  \infer{}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
11
  {\prop * \Exists\var.\propB \provesIff \Exists\var. \prop * \propB}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
12
13
14
15
16

  \infer{}
  {\prop * \Exists\var.\propB \proves \Exists\var. \prop * \propB}

  \infer{}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
17
  {\always(\prop*\propB) \provesIff \always\prop * \always\propB}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25

  \infer{}
  {\always(\prop \Ra \propB) \proves \always\prop \Ra \always\propB}

  \infer{}
  {\always(\prop \wand \propB) \proves \always\prop \wand \always\propB}

  \infer{}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
26
  {\always(\prop \wand \propB) \provesIff \always(\prop \Ra \propB)}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37

  \infer{}
  {\later(\prop \Ra \propB) \proves \later\prop \Ra \later\propB}

  \infer{}
  {\later(\prop \wand \propB) \proves \later\prop \wand \later\propB}

  \infer
  {\pfctx, \later\prop \proves \prop}
  {\pfctx \proves \prop}
\end{mathparpagebreakable}
38

39
40
41
42
43
44
\paragraph{Persistent assertions.}
\begin{defn}
  An assertion $\prop$ is \emph{persistent} if $\prop \proves \always\prop$.
\end{defn}

Of course, $\always\prop$ is persistent for any $\prop$.
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
45
Furthermore, by the proof rules given above, $t = t'$ as well as $\ownGGhost{\mcore\melt}$ and $\knowInv\iname\prop$ are persistent.
46
47
48
49
Persistence is preserved by conjunction, disjunction, separating conjunction as well as universal and existential quantification.

In our proofs, we will implicitly add and remove $\always$ from persistent assertions as necessary, and generally treat them like normal, non-linear assumptions.

Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
\paragraph{Timeless assertions.}

We can show that the following additional closure properties hold for timeless assertions:

\begin{mathparpagebreakable}
  \infer
  {\vctx \proves \timeless{\prop} \and \vctx \proves \timeless{\propB}}
  {\vctx \proves \timeless{\prop \land \propB}}

  \infer
  {\vctx \proves \timeless{\prop} \and \vctx \proves \timeless{\propB}}
  {\vctx \proves \timeless{\prop \lor \propB}}

  \infer
  {\vctx \proves \timeless{\prop} \and \vctx \proves \timeless{\propB}}
  {\vctx \proves \timeless{\prop * \propB}}

  \infer
  {\vctx \proves \timeless{\prop}}
  {\vctx \proves \timeless{\always\prop}}
\end{mathparpagebreakable}


73
74
\subsection{Program logic}

Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
75
Hoare triples and view shifts are syntactic sugar for weakest (liberal) preconditions and primitive view shifts, respectively:
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
\[
\hoare{\prop}{\expr}{\Ret\val.\propB}[\mask] \eqdef \always{(\prop \Ra \wpre{\expr}{\lambda\Ret\val.\propB}[\mask])}
\qquad\qquad
\begin{aligned}
\prop \vs[\mask_1][\mask_2] \propB &\eqdef \always{(\prop \Ra \pvs[\mask_1][\mask_2] {\propB})} \\
\prop \vsE[\mask_1][\mask_2] \propB &\eqdef \prop \vs[\mask_1][\mask_2] \propB \land \propB \vs[\mask2][\mask_1] \prop
\end{aligned}
\]
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
84
We write just one mask for a view shift when $\mask_1 = \mask_2$.
85
86
Clearly, all of these assertions are persistent.
The convention for omitted masks is similar to the base logic:
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
87
88
89
An omitted $\mask$ is $\top$ for Hoare triples and $\emptyset$ for view shifts.


90
91
\paragraph{View shifts.}~
The following rules can be derived for view shifts.
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
92

93
94
\begin{mathparpagebreakable}
\inferH{vs-update}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
95
96
97
  {\melt \mupd \meltsB}
  {\ownGGhost{\melt} \vs \exists \meltB \in \meltsB.\; \ownGGhost{\meltB}}
\and
98
\inferH{vs-trans}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
99
100
101
  {\prop \vs[\mask_1][\mask_2] \propB \and \propB \vs[\mask_2][\mask_3] \propC \and \mask_2 \subseteq \mask_1 \cup \mask_3}
  {\prop \vs[\mask_1][\mask_3] \propC}
\and
102
\inferH{vs-imp}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
103
104
105
  {\always{(\prop \Ra \propB)}}
  {\prop \vs[\emptyset] \propB}
\and
106
\inferH{vs-mask-frame}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
107
  {\prop \vs[\mask_1][\mask_2] \propB}
108
  {\prop \vs[\mask_1 \uplus \mask'][\mask_2 \uplus \mask'] \propB}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
109
\and
110
111
112
113
114
\inferH{vs-frame}
  {\prop \vs[\mask_1][\mask_2] \propB}
  {\prop * \propC \vs[\mask_1][\mask_2] \propB * \propC}
\and
\inferH{vs-timeless}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
115
116
117
  {\timeless{\prop}}
  {\later \prop \vs \prop}
\and
118
119
120
121
122
\inferH{vs-allocI}
  {\infinite(\mask)}
  {\later{\prop} \vs[\mask] \exists \iname\in\mask.\; \knowInv{\iname}{\prop}}
\and
\axiomH{vs-openI}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
123
124
  {\knowInv{\iname}{\prop} \proves \TRUE \vs[\{ \iname \} ][\emptyset] \later \prop}
\and
125
\axiomH{vs-closeI}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
126
127
  {\knowInv{\iname}{\prop} \proves \later \prop \vs[\emptyset][\{ \iname \} ] \TRUE }

128
\inferHB{vs-disj}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
129
130
131
  {\prop \vs[\mask_1][\mask_2] \propC \and \propB \vs[\mask_1][\mask_2] \propC}
  {\prop \lor \propB \vs[\mask_1][\mask_2] \propC}
\and
132
\inferHB{vs-exist}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
133
134
135
  {\All \var. (\prop \vs[\mask_1][\mask_2] \propB)}
  {(\Exists \var. \prop) \vs[\mask_1][\mask_2] \propB}
\and
136
\inferHB{vs-box}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
137
  {\always\propB \proves \prop \vs[\mask_1][\mask_2] \propC}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
138
139
  {\prop \land \always{\propB} \vs[\mask_1][\mask_2] \propC}
 \and
140
\inferH{vs-false}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
141
142
  {}
  {\FALSE \vs[\mask_1][\mask_2] \prop }
143
\end{mathparpagebreakable}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
144
145


146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
\paragraph{Hoare triples.}
The following rules can be derived for Hoare triples.

\begin{mathparpagebreakable}
\inferH{Ht-ret}
  {}
  {\hoare{\TRUE}{\valB}{\Ret\val. \val = \valB}[\mask]}
\and
\inferH{Ht-bind}
  {\text{$\lctx$ is a context} \and \hoare{\prop}{\expr}{\Ret\val. \propB}[\mask] \\
   \All \val. \hoare{\propB}{\lctx(\val)}{\Ret\valB.\propC}[\mask]}
  {\hoare{\prop}{\lctx(\expr)}{\Ret\valB.\propC}[\mask]}
\and
\inferH{Ht-csq}
  {\prop \vs \prop' \\
    \hoare{\prop'}{\expr}{\Ret\val.\propB'}[\mask] \\   
   \All \val. \propB' \vs \propB}
  {\hoare{\prop}{\expr}{\Ret\val.\propB}[\mask]}
\and
\inferH{Ht-mask-weaken}
  {\hoare{\prop}{\expr}{\Ret\val. \propB}[\mask]}
  {\hoare{\prop}{\expr}{\Ret\val. \propB}[\mask \uplus \mask']}
\\\\
\inferH{Ht-frame}
  {\hoare{\prop}{\expr}{\Ret\val. \propB}[\mask]}
  {\hoare{\prop * \propC}{\expr}{\Ret\val. \propB * \propC}[\mask]}
\and
\inferH{Ht-frame-step}
  {\hoare{\prop}{\expr}{\Ret\val. \propB}[\mask] \and \toval(\expr) = \bot}
  {\hoare{\prop * \later\propC}{\expr}{\Ret\val. \propB * \propC}[\mask]}
\and
\inferH{Ht-atomic}
  {\prop \vs[\mask \uplus \mask'][\mask] \prop' \\
    \hoare{\prop'}{\expr}{\Ret\val.\propB'}[\mask] \\   
   \All\val. \propB' \vs[\mask][\mask \uplus \mask'] \propB \\
   \physatomic{\expr}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
182
  }
183
  {\hoare{\prop}{\expr}{\Ret\val.\propB}[\mask \uplus \mask']}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
184
\and
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
\inferHB{Ht-disj}
  {\hoare{\prop}{\expr}{\Ret\val.\propC}[\mask] \and \hoare{\propB}{\expr}{\Ret\val.\propC}[\mask]}
  {\hoare{\prop \lor \propB}{\expr}{\Ret\val.\propC}[\mask]}
\and
\inferHB{Ht-exist}
  {\All \var. \hoare{\prop}{\expr}{\Ret\val.\propB}[\mask]}
  {\hoare{\Exists \var. \prop}{\expr}{\Ret\val.\propB}[\mask]}
\and
\inferHB{Ht-box}
  {\always\propB \proves \hoare{\prop}{\expr}{\Ret\val.\propC}[\mask]}
  {\hoare{\prop \land \always{\propB}}{\expr}{\Ret\val.\propC}[\mask]}
\and
\inferH{Ht-false}
  {}
  {\hoare{\FALSE}{\expr}{\Ret \val. \prop}[\mask]}
\end{mathparpagebreakable}
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
201

Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
202
203
\subsection{Global Functor and ghost ownership}
\ralf{Describe this.}
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235

% \subsection{Global monoid}

% Hereinafter we assume the global monoid (served up as a parameter to Iris) is obtained from a family of monoids $(M_i)_{i \in I}$ by first applying the construction for finite partial functions to each~(\Sref{sec:fpfunm}), and then applying the product construction~(\Sref{sec:prodm}):
% \[ M \eqdef \prod_{i \in I} \textdom{GhName} \fpfn M_i \]
% We don't care so much about what concretely $\textdom{GhName}$ is, as long as it is countable and infinite.
% We write $\ownGhost{\gname}{\melt : M_i}$ (or just $\ownGhost{\gname}{\melt}$ if $M_i$ is clear from the context) for $\ownGGhost{[i \mapsto [\gname \mapsto \melt]]}$ when $\melt \in \mcarp {M_i}$, and for $\FALSE$ when $\melt = \mzero_{M_i}$.
% In other words, $\ownGhost{\gname}{\melt : M_i}$ asserts that in the current state of monoid $M_i$, the name $\gname$ is allocated and has at least value $\melt$.

% From~\ruleref{FpUpd} and the multiplications and frame-preserving updates in~\Sref{sec:prodm} and~\Sref{sec:fpfunm}, we have the following derived rules.
% \begin{mathpar}
% 	\axiomH{NewGhost}{
% 		\TRUE \vs \Exists\gname. \ownGhost\gname{\melt : M_i}
% 	}
% 	\and
% 	\inferH{GhostUpd}
%     {\melt \mupd_{M_i} B}
%     {\ownGhost\gname{\melt : M_i} \vs \Exists \meltB\in B. \ownGhost\gname{\meltB : M_i}}
%   \and
%   \axiomH{GhostEq}
%     {\ownGhost\gname{\melt : M_i} * \ownGhost\gname{\meltB : M_i} \Lra \ownGhost\gname{\melt\mtimes\meltB : M_i}}

%   \axiomH{GhostUnit}
%     {\TRUE \Ra \ownGhost{\gname}{\munit : M_i}}

%   \axiomH{GhostZero}
%     {\ownGhost\gname{\mzero : M_i} \Ra \FALSE}

%   \axiomH{GhostTimeless}
%     {\timeless{\ownGhost\gname{\melt : M_i}}}
% \end{mathpar}

Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
236
237
238
\subsection{Invariant identifier namespaces}
\ralf{Describe this.}

239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
% \subsection{STSs with interpretation}\label{sec:stsinterp}

% Building on \Sref{sec:stsmon}, after constructing the monoid $\STSMon{\STSS}$ for a particular STS, we can use an invariant to tie an interpretation, $\pred : \STSS \to \Prop$, to the STS's current state, recovering CaReSL-style reasoning~\cite{caresl}.

% An STS invariant asserts authoritative ownership of an STS's current state and that state's interpretation:
% \begin{align*}
%   \STSInv(\STSS, \pred, \gname) \eqdef{}& \Exists s \in \STSS. \ownGhost{\gname}{(s, \STSS, \emptyset):\STSMon{\STSS}} * \pred(s) \\
%   \STS(\STSS, \pred, \gname, \iname) \eqdef{}& \knowInv{\iname}{\STSInv(\STSS, \pred, \gname)}
% \end{align*}

% We can specialize \ruleref{NewInv}, \ruleref{InvOpen}, and \ruleref{InvClose} to STS invariants:
% \begin{mathpar}
%  \inferH{NewSts}
%   {\infinite(\mask)}
%   {\later\pred(s) \vs[\mask] \Exists \iname \in \mask, \gname.   \STS(\STSS, \pred, \gname, \iname) * \ownGhost{\gname}{(s, \STST \setminus \STSL(s)) : \STSMon{\STSS}}}
%  \and
%  \axiomH{StsOpen}
%   {  \STS(\STSS, \pred, \gname, \iname) \vdash \ownGhost{\gname}{(s_0, T) : \STSMon{\STSS}} \vsE[\{\iname\}][\emptyset] \Exists s\in \upclose(\{s_0\}, T). \later\pred(s) * \ownGhost{\gname}{(s, \upclose(\{s_0\}, T), T):\STSMon{\STSS}}}
%  \and
%  \axiomH{StsClose}
%   {  \STS(\STSS, \pred, \gname, \iname), (s, T) \ststrans (s', T')  \proves \later\pred(s') * \ownGhost{\gname}{(s, S, T):\STSMon{\STSS}} \vs[\emptyset][\{\iname\}] \ownGhost{\gname}{(s', T') : \STSMon{\STSS}} }
% \end{mathpar}
% \begin{proof}
% \ruleref{NewSts} uses \ruleref{NewGhost} to allocate $\ownGhost{\gname}{(s, \upclose(s, T), T) : \STSMon{\STSS}}$ where $T \eqdef \STST \setminus \STSL(s)$, and \ruleref{NewInv}.

% \ruleref{StsOpen} just uses \ruleref{InvOpen} and \ruleref{InvClose} on $\iname$, and the monoid equality $(s, \upclose(\{s_0\}, T), T) = (s, \STSS, \emptyset) \mtimes (\munit, \upclose(\{s_0\}, T), T)$.

% \ruleref{StsClose} applies \ruleref{StsStep} and \ruleref{InvClose}.
% \end{proof}
268

269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
% Using these view shifts, we can prove STS variants of the invariant rules \ruleref{Inv} and \ruleref{VSInv}~(compare the former to CaReSL's island update rule~\cite{caresl}):
% \begin{mathpar}
%  \inferH{Sts}
%   {\All s \in \upclose(\{s_0\}, T). \hoare{\later\pred(s) * P}{\expr}{\Ret \val. \Exists s', T'. (s, T) \ststrans (s', T') * \later\pred(s') * Q}[\mask]
%    \and \physatomic{\expr}}
%   {  \STS(\STSS, \pred, \gname, \iname) \vdash \hoare{\ownGhost{\gname}{(s_0, T):\STSMon{\STSS}} * P}{\expr}{\Ret \val. \Exists s', T'. \ownGhost{\gname}{(s', T'):\STSMon{\STSS}} * Q}[\mask \uplus \{\iname\}]}
%  \and
%  \inferH{VSSts}
%   {\forall s \in \upclose(\{s_0\}, T).\; \later\pred(s) * P \vs[\mask_1][\mask_2] \exists s', T'.\; (s, T) \ststrans (s', T') * \later\pred(s') * Q}
%   {  \STS(\STSS, \pred, \gname, \iname) \vdash \ownGhost{\gname}{(s_0, T):\STSMon{\STSS}} * P \vs[\mask_1 \uplus \{\iname\}][\mask_2 \uplus \{\iname\}] \Exists s', T'. \ownGhost{\gname}{(s', T'):\STSMon{\STSS}} * Q}
% \end{mathpar}

% \begin{proof}[Proof of \ruleref{Sts}]\label{pf:sts}
%  We have to show
%  \[\hoare{\ownGhost{\gname}{(s_0, T):\STSMon{\STSS}} * P}{\expr}{\Ret \val. \Exists s', T'. \ownGhost{\gname}{(s', T'):\STSMon{\STSS}} * Q}[\mask \uplus \{\iname\}]\]
%  where $\val$, $s'$, $T'$ are free in $Q$.
285
 
286
287
%  First, by \ruleref{ACsq} with \ruleref{StsOpen} and \ruleref{StsClose} (after moving $(s, T) \ststrans (s', T')$ into the view shift using \ruleref{VSBoxOut}), it suffices to show
%  \[\hoareV{\Exists s\in \upclose(\{s_0\}, T). \later\pred(s) * \ownGhost{\gname}{(s, \upclose(\{s_0\}, T), T)} * P}{\expr}{\Ret \val. \Exists s, T, S, s', T'. (s, T) \ststrans (s', T') * \later\pred(s') * \ownGhost{\gname}{(s, S, T):\STSMon{\STSS}} * Q(\val, s', T')}[\mask]\]
288

289
290
291
%  Now, use \ruleref{Exist} to move the $s$ from the precondition into the context and use \ruleref{Csq} to (i)~fix the $s$ and $T$ in the postcondition to be the same as in the precondition, and (ii)~fix $S \eqdef \upclose(\{s_0\}, T)$.
%  It remains to show:
%  \[\hoareV{s\in \upclose(\{s_0\}, T) * \later\pred(s) * \ownGhost{\gname}{(s, \upclose(\{s_0\}, T), T)} * P}{\expr}{\Ret \val. \Exists s', T'. (s, T) \ststrans (s', T') * \later\pred(s') * \ownGhost{\gname}{(s, \upclose(\{s_0\}, T), T)} * Q(\val, s', T')}[\mask]\]
292
 
293
294
%  Finally, use \ruleref{BoxOut} to move $s\in \upclose(\{s_0\}, T)$ into the context, and \ruleref{Frame} on $\ownGhost{\gname}{(s, \upclose(\{s_0\}, T), T)}$:
%  \[s\in \upclose(\{s_0\}, T) \vdash \hoare{\later\pred(s) * P}{\expr}{\Ret \val. \Exists s', T'. (s, T) \ststrans (s', T') * \later\pred(s') * Q(\val, s', T')}[\mask]\]
295
 
296
%  This holds by our premise.
Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
297
% \end{proof}
298

299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
% % \begin{proof}[Proof of \ruleref{VSSts}]
% % This is similar to above, so we only give the proof in short notation:

% % \hproof{%
% % 	Context: $\knowInv\iname{\STSInv(\STSS, \pred, \gname)}$ \\
% % 	\pline[\mask_1 \uplus \{\iname\}]{
% % 		\ownGhost\gname{(s_0, T)} * P
% % 	} \\
% % 	\pline[\mask_1]{%
% % 		\Exists s. \later\pred(s) * \ownGhost\gname{(s, S, T)} * P
% % 	} \qquad by \ruleref{StsOpen} \\
% % 	Context: $s \in S \eqdef \upclose(\{s_0\}, T)$ \\
% % 	\pline[\mask_2]{%
% % 		 \Exists s', T'. \later\pred(s') * Q(s', T') * \ownGhost\gname{(s, S, T)}
% % 	} \qquad by premiss \\
% % 	Context: $(s, T) \ststrans (s', T')$ \\
% % 	\pline[\mask_2 \uplus \{\iname\}]{
% % 		\ownGhost\gname{(s', T')} * Q(s', T')
% % 	} \qquad by \ruleref{StsClose}
% % }
% % \end{proof}

% \subsection{Authoritative monoids with interpretation}\label{sec:authinterp}

% Building on \Sref{sec:auth}, after constructing the monoid $\auth{M}$ for a cancellative monoid $M$, we can tie an interpretation, $\pred : \mcarp{M} \to \Prop$, to the authoritative element of $M$, recovering reasoning that is close to the sharing rule in~\cite{krishnaswami+:icfp12}.

% Let $\pred_\bot$ be the extension of $\pred$ to $\mcar{M}$ with $\pred_\bot(\mzero) = \FALSE$.
% Now define
% \begin{align*}
%   \AuthInv(M, \pred, \gname) \eqdef{}& \exists \melt \in \mcar{M}.\; \ownGhost{\gname}{\authfull \melt:\auth{M}} * \pred_\bot(\melt) \\
%   \Auth(M, \pred, \gname, \iname) \eqdef{}& M~\textlog{cancellative} \land \knowInv{\iname}{\AuthInv(M, \pred, \gname)}
% \end{align*}

% The frame-preserving updates for $\auth{M}$ gives rise to the following view shifts:
% \begin{mathpar}
%  \inferH{NewAuth}
%   {\infinite(\mask) \and M~\textlog{cancellative}}
%   {\later\pred_\bot(a) \vs[\mask] \exists \iname \in \mask, \gname.\; \Auth(M, \pred, \gname, \iname) * \ownGhost{\gname}{\authfrag a : \auth{M}}}
%  \and
%  \axiomH{AuthOpen}
%   {\Auth(M, \pred, \gname, \iname) \vdash \ownGhost{\gname}{\authfrag \melt : \auth{M}} \vsE[\{\iname\}][\emptyset] \exists \melt_f.\; \later\pred_\bot(\melt \mtimes \melt_f) * \ownGhost{\gname}{\authfull \melt \mtimes \melt_f, \authfrag a:\auth{M}}}
%  \and
%  \axiomH{AuthClose}
%   {\Auth(M, \pred, \gname, \iname) \vdash \later\pred_\bot(\meltB \mtimes \melt_f) * \ownGhost{\gname}{\authfull a \mtimes \melt_f, \authfrag a:\auth{M}} \vs[\emptyset][\{\iname\}] \ownGhost{\gname}{\authfrag \meltB : \auth{M}} }
% \end{mathpar}

% These view shifts in turn can be used to prove variants of the invariant rules:
% \begin{mathpar}
%  \inferH{Auth}
%   {\forall \melt_f.\; \hoare{\later\pred_\bot(a \mtimes \melt_f) * P}{\expr}{\Ret\val. \exists \meltB.\; \later\pred_\bot(\meltB\mtimes \melt_f) * Q}[\mask]
%    \and \physatomic{\expr}}
%   {\Auth(M, \pred, \gname, \iname) \vdash \hoare{\ownGhost{\gname}{\authfrag a:\auth{M}} * P}{\expr}{\Ret\val. \exists \meltB.\; \ownGhost{\gname}{\authfrag \meltB:\auth{M}} * Q}[\mask \uplus \{\iname\}]}
%  \and
%  \inferH{VSAuth}
%   {\forall \melt_f.\; \later\pred_\bot(a \mtimes \melt_f) * P \vs[\mask_1][\mask_2] \exists \meltB.\; \later\pred_\bot(\meltB \mtimes \melt_f) * Q(\meltB)}
%   {\Auth(M, \pred, \gname, \iname) \vdash
%    \ownGhost{\gname}{\authfrag a:\auth{M}} * P \vs[\mask_1 \uplus \{\iname\}][\mask_2 \uplus \{\iname\}]
%    \exists \meltB.\; \ownGhost{\gname}{\authfrag \meltB:\auth{M}} * Q(\meltB)}
% \end{mathpar}


% \subsection{Ghost heap}
% \label{sec:ghostheap}%

% We define a simple ghost heap with fractional permissions.
% Some modules require a few ghost names per module instance to properly manage ghost state, but would like to expose to clients a single logical name (avoiding clutter).
% In such cases we use these ghost heaps.

% We seek to implement the following interface:
% \newcommand{\GRefspecmaps}{\textsf{GMapsTo}}%
% \begin{align*}
%  \exists& {\fgmapsto[]} : \textsort{Val} \times \mathbb{Q}_{>} \times \textsort{Val} \ra \textsort{Prop}.\;\\
%   & \All x, q, v. x \fgmapsto[q] v \Ra x \fgmapsto[q] v \land q \in (0, 1] \\
%   &\forall x, q_1, q_2, v, w.\; x \fgmapsto[q_1] v * x \fgmapsto[q_2] w \Leftrightarrow x \fgmapsto[q_1 + q_2] v * v = w\\
%   & \forall v.\; \TRUE \vs[\emptyset] \exists x.\; x \fgmapsto[1] v \\
%   & \forall x, v, w.\; x \fgmapsto[1] v \vs[\emptyset] x \fgmapsto[1] w
% \end{align*}
% We write $x \fgmapsto v$ for $\exists q.\; x \fgmapsto[q] v$ and $x \gmapsto v$ for $x \fgmapsto[1] v$.
% Note that $x \fgmapsto v$ is duplicable but cannot be boxed (as it depends on resources); \ie we have $x \fgmapsto v \Lra x \fgmapsto v * x \fgmapsto v$ but not $x \fgmapsto v \Ra \always x \fgmapsto v$.

% To implement this interface, allocate an instance $\gname_G$ of $\FHeap(\textdom{Val})$ and define
% \[
% 	x \fgmapsto[q] v \eqdef
% 	  \begin{cases}
%     	\ownGhost{\gname_G}{x \mapsto (q, v)} & \text{if $q \in (0, 1]$} \\
%     	\FALSE & \text{otherwise}
%     \end{cases}
% \]
% The view shifts in the specification follow immediately from \ruleref{GhostUpd} and the frame-preserving updates in~\Sref{sec:fheapm}.
% The first implication is immediate from the definition.
% The second implication follows by case distinction on $q_1 + q_2 \in (0, 1]$.
390

Ralf Jung's avatar
Ralf Jung committed
391
392
393
394
395

%%% Local Variables:
%%% mode: latex
%%% TeX-master: "iris"
%%% End: